Items related to Rethinking Language, Mind, and Meaning (Carl G. Hempel...

Rethinking Language, Mind, and Meaning (Carl G. Hempel Lecture Series): 5 - Hardcover

 
9780691160450: Rethinking Language, Mind, and Meaning (Carl G. Hempel Lecture Series): 5

Synopsis

In this book, Scott Soames argues that the revolution in the study of language and mind that has taken place since the late nineteenth century must be rethought. The central insight in the reigning tradition is that propositions are representational. To know the meaning of a sentence or the content of a belief requires knowing which things it represents as being which ways, and therefore knowing what the world must be like if it is to conform to how the sentence or belief represents it. These are truth conditions of the sentence or belief. But meanings and representational contents are not truth conditions, and there is more to propositions than representational content. In addition to imposing conditions the world must satisfy if it is to be true, a proposition may also impose conditions on minds that entertain it. The study of mind and language cannot advance further without a conception of propositions that allows them to have contents of both of these sorts. Soames provides it. He does so by arguing that propositions are repeatable, purely representational cognitive acts or operations that represent the world as being a certain way, while requiring minds that perform them to satisfy certain cognitive conditions. Because they have these two types of content--one facing the world and one facing the mind--pairs of propositions can be representationally identical but cognitively distinct. Using this breakthrough, Soames offers new solutions to several of the most perplexing problems in the philosophy of language and mind.

"synopsis" may belong to another edition of this title.

About the Author

Scott Soames is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy and director of the School of Philosophy at the University of Southern California. He is the author of many books, including The Analytic Tradition in Philosophy, Volume 1; Analytic Philosophy in America; Philosophy of Language; Philosophical Essays; and Philosophical Analysis in the Twentieth Century (all Princeton).

From the Back Cover

"This is a very significant and original contribution to the philosophy of language, centering on a new way of thinking about propositions. Previous authors have treated propositions as abstract entities that speakers and hearers are aware of and that constitute the meanings or contents of sentences. But Soames argues persuasively that propositions are best thought of as things people do. In developing this idea, he shows how his proposal solves significant difficulties in the philosophy of language. This book will make a huge impact on the subject."--Gilbert Harman, Princeton University

"This is a brilliant book and it will be extremely influential. It lays out Soames's important theory of propositions, and significantly extends that theory to solve central problems in the foundations of the study of mind and language. Soames has gone further than anyone else in trying to use a theory of the metaphysics of propositions to illuminate issues in the theory of content."--Jeff Speaks, University of Notre Dame

From the Inside Flap

"This is a very significant and original contribution to the philosophy of language, centering on a new way of thinking about propositions. Previous authors have treated propositions as abstract entities that speakers and hearers are aware of and that constitute the meanings or contents of sentences. But Soames argues persuasively that propositions are best thought of as things people do. In developing this idea, he shows how his proposal solves significant difficulties in the philosophy of language. This book will make a huge impact on the subject."--Gilbert Harman, Princeton University

"This is a brilliant book and it will be extremely influential. It lays out Soames s important theory of propositions, and significantly extends that theory to solve central problems in the foundations of the study of mind and language. Soames has gone further than anyone else in trying to use a theory of the metaphysics of propositions to illuminate issues in the theory of content."--Jeff Speaks, University of Notre Dame

Excerpt. © Reprinted by permission. All rights reserved.

Rethinking Language, Mind, and Meaning

By SCOTT SOAMES

PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS

Copyright © 2015 Princeton University Press
All rights reserved.
ISBN: 978-0-691-16045-0

Contents

Acknowledgments, ix,
Chapter 1 The Need for New Foundations, 1,
Chapter 2 The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Information, 15,
Chapter 3 Thinking of Oneself, the Present Moment, and the Actual World-State, 46,
Chapter 4 Linguistic Cognition, Understanding, and Millian Modes of Presentation, 67,
Chapter 5 Perceptual and Demonstrative Modes of Presentation, 96,
Chapter 6 Recognition of Recurrence, 117,
Chapter 7 Believing, Asserting, and Communicating Propositions of Limited Accessibility, 143,
Chapter 8 Recognition of Recurrence Revisited, 156,
Chapter 9 Situating Cognitive Propositions in a Broader Context, 164,
Chapter 10 Overcoming Objections, 208,
Chapter 11 Worries, Opportunities, and Unsolved Problems, 225,
References, 235,
Index, 239,


CHAPTER 1

The Need for New Foundations


In this book, I will argue that the revolution in the study of language, mind, and meaning led by advances in philosophical logic from Frege through Tarski, Kripke, Montague, and Kaplan must be reconceptualized. Although much progress has been made by adapting intensional logic to the study of natural language, the resulting theoretical framework has limitations that require rethinking much of what has guided us up to now. I will begin by sketching where we are in the study of linguistic meaning and how we got there, after which I will identify three main ways in which I believe the current theoretical framework must change.

The story begins with the development of symbolic logic by Gottlob Frege and Bertrand Russell at the end of the nineteenth and beginning of the twentieth centuries. Initially, their goal was to answer two questions in the philosophy of mathematics: What is the source of mathematical knowledge? and What are numbers? They answered (roughly) that logic is the source of mathematical knowledge, that zero is the set of concepts true of nothing, that one is the set of concepts true something, and only that thing, that two is the set of concepts true of some distinct x and y, and nothing else, and so on. Since the concept being non-self-identical is true of nothing, it is a member of zero; since the concept being the Hempel lecturer in 2013 is true of me and only me, it is a member of the number one; since the concept being my son is true of Greg and Brian Soames, and only them, it is a member of the number two. Other integers follow in train. Since numbers are sets of concepts, the successor of a number n is the set of concepts F such that for some x of which F is true, the concept being an F which is not identical to x is a member of n. Natural numbers are defined as those things that are members of every set that contains zero, and that, whenever it contains something, always contains its successor. Multiplication is defined as repeated addition, while addition is defined as repeated application of the successor function. In this way arithmetic was derived from what Frege and Russell took to be pure logic. When, in similar fashion, classical results of higher mathematics were derived from arithmetic, it was thought that all classical mathematics could be so generated. So, logic was seen the foundation of all mathematical knowledge.

That, at any rate, was the breathtaking dream of Frege and Russell. The reality was more complicated. Their first step was the development of the predicate calculus (of first and higher orders), which combined truth-functional logic, familiar from the Stoics onward, with a powerful new account of generality supplanting the more limited syllogistic logic dating back to Aristotle. The key move was to trade the subject/predicate distinction of syllogistic logic for an expanded version of the function/argument distinction from mathematics. Applied to quantification, this meant treating the claim that something is F as predicating being true of something of the property being F or, in Russell's convenient formulation, of the function that maps an object onto the proposition that it is F, while treating the claim that everything is F as predicating being true of each object of that property or function. The crucial point, resulting in a vast increase in expressive power, is the analysis of all and some as expressing higher-order properties of properties or propositional functions expressed by formulas of arbitrary complexity.

Although the first-order fragment of Frege's system was sound and complete—in the sense of proving all and only genuine logical truths—the concepts needed to define and prove this (while also proving that the higher-order system was sound but, like all such systems, incomplete) were still fifty years away. In itself, this didn't defeat the reduction of mathematics to logic. More serious was the intertwining of this early stage of modern logic with what we now call "naïve set theory"—according to which for every stateable condition on objects there is a set (perhaps empty, perhaps not) of all and only the things satisfying it. To think of this as a principle of logic is to think that talk of something's being so-and-so is interchangeable with talk of its being in the set of so-and-so's.

When Russell's paradox demonstrated the contradiction at the heart of this system, it quickly became clear that the principles required to generate sets without falling into contradiction are less obvious, and open to greater doubt, than the arithmetical principles that Frege and Russell hoped to derive from them. This undercut the initial epistemological motivation for reducing mathematics to logic. Partly for this reason, the subsequent boundary that grew up between logic and set theory was one in which the latter came to be viewed as itself an elementary mathematical theory, rather than a part of logic. Reductions of mathematical theories to set theory could still be done, with illuminating results for the foundations of mathematics, but the philosophical payoff was not what Frege and Russell initially hoped for.

This philosophical shortcoming was compensated by the birth of new deductive disciplines—proof theory and model theory—to study the powerful new logical systems that had been developed. A modern system of logic consists of a formally defined language, plus a proof procedure, often in the form of a set of axioms and rules of inference. A proof is a finite sequence of lines each of which is an axiom or a formula obtainable from earlier lines by inference rules. Whether or not something counts as a proof is decidable merely by inspecting the formula on each line, and determining whether it is an axiom, and, if it isn't, whether it bears the structural relation to earlier lines required by the rules. Since these are trivially decidable questions, it can always be decided whether something counts as a proof, thus forestalling the need to prove that something is a proof. In a purely logical (first-order) system, the aim is to prove all and only the logical truths, and to be able to derive from any statement all and only its logical consequences.

These notions are defined semantically. To think of them in this way is to think of them as having something to do with meaning. Although this wasn't exactly how the founder of model theory, Alfred Tarski, initially conceived them, it is how his work was interpreted by Rudolf Carnap and many who followed. The key idea is that we can study the meaning of sentences by studying what would make them true. This is done by constructing abstract models of the world and checking to see which sentences are true in which models. When a sentence is true in all models it is a logical truth; when the truth of one sentence in a model always guarantees the truth of another, the second is a logical consequence of the first; when two sentences are always true together or false together they are logically equivalent, which is the logician's approximation of sameness of meaning.

By the mid-1930s, the model and proof theories of the first- and second-order predicate calculi were well understood and inspiring new projects. One was modal logic, which introduced an operator it is logically/analytically/necessarily true that—the prefixing of which to a standard logical truth produces a truth. Apart from confusion about what logical, semantic, or metaphysical notion was to be captured, the technical ideas soon emerged. Since the new operators are defined in terms of truth at model-like elements, logical models for modal languages had to contain such elements, now dubbed possible world-states, thought of as ways the world could have been. This development strengthened the Fregean idea that for a (declarative) sentence S to be meaningful is for S to represent the world as being a certain way, which is to impose conditions the world must satisfy if S is to be true.

Hence, it was thought, meaning could be studied by using the syntactic structure of sentences plus the representational contents of their parts to specify their truth conditions. With the advent of modality, these conditions were for the first time strong enough to approximate the meanings of sentences. To learn what the world would have to be like to conform to how a sentence (of a certain sort) represents it is to learn something approximating its meaning. The significance of this advance for the study of language can hardly be overstated. Having reached this stage, we had both a putative answer to the question What is the meaning of a sentence? and a systematic way of studying it.

This is roughly where the philosophically inspired study of linguistically encoded information stood in 1960. Since then, philosophers, philosophical logicians, and theoretical linguists have expanded the framework to cover large fragments of human languages. Their research program starts with the predicate calculi and is enriched piece by piece, as more natural-language constructions are added. Modal operators include it is necessarily the case that, it could have been the case that, and the counterfactual operator if it had been the case that ____, then it would have been the case that ____. Operators involving time and tense can be treated along similar lines. Generalized quantifiers have been added, as have adverbs of quantification, and propositional attitude verbs such as believe, expect, and know. We also have accounts of adverbial modifiers, comparatives, intensional transitives, indexicals, and demonstratives. At each stage, a language fragment for which we already have a truth-theoretic semantics is expanded to include more features found in natural language. As the research program advances, the fragments of which we have a good truth-theoretic grasp become more powerful and more fully natural language-like. Although there are legitimate doubts about whether all aspects of natural language can be squeezed into one or another version of this representational paradigm, the prospects of extending the results so far achieved justify optimism about eventually arriving at a time when vastly enriched descendants of the original systems of Frege and Russell approach the expressive power of natural language, allowing us to understand the most basic productive principles by which information is linguistically encoded.

This, in a nutshell, is the dominant semantic conception in theoretical linguistics today. If all that remained were to fill in gaps and flesh out empirical details, philosophers would have done most of what was needed to transform their initial philosophical questions about mathematics into scientific questions about language. However, we haven't yet reached that point. While the dominant conception has made progress in using truth conditions to model representational contents of sentences, it has not paid enough attention to the demands that using and understanding language place on agents. Given the logical, mathematical, and philosophical origins of the enterprise, it could hardly have been otherwise. When what was at stake was, primarily, the investigation of the logical, analytic, or necessary consequences of mathematical and scientific statements, there was no theoretically significant gap to be considered between what a sentence means and the claim it is used to make, and hence no need either to investigate how speaker-hearers might fill such gaps or to study what understanding and using a language consist in, and no need to individuate thoughts or meanings beyond necessary equivalence.

There have, to be sure, been important attempts to address these issues as the dominant semantic model has extended its reach beyond the formal languages of logic, mathematics, and science. We need, for example, to look no further than David Kaplan's logic of demonstratives, to find a way of accommodating the idea that what a sentence means and what it is standardly used to say are—though systematically related—not always the same. What we don't find in Kaplan, or in the dominant approach generally, is any retreat from the idea that advances in the understanding the semantics of natural language are closely and inextricably tied to advances in extending the reach of the methods of formal logic and model theory. This, I believe, must change if we are to reach our goal of founding a truly scientific study of language and information.

In this book, I will outline three steps in that direction. First, I will use examples involving several linguistic constructions to argue that we must stop oversimplifying the relationship between the information semantically encoded by (a use of) a sentence (in a context), on the one hand, and the assertions it is there used to make, the beliefs it is there used to express, and the information there conveyed by an utterance of it, on the other. It has often been assumed that the semantic content of a sentence is identical, or nearly so, with what one who accepts it thereby believes, and with what one who utters it thereby asserts. This is far too simple; there is a significant gap between the semantic contents of sentences and the information contents of their uses.

Second, I will argue that we need to pay more attention to what understanding a linguistic expression E requires—beyond, or other than, knowing of the representational content of E that it is the content of E. It is often assumed that since meaning is semantically encoded information, and since the information encoded by a nonindexical sentence S is the proposition p it expresses, understanding S is knowing of S that it encodes p. I will argue that this is not so. Semantic knowledge of this simple representational sort is insufficient for understanding because, as I will illustrate in chapter 4, to understand a word, phrase, or sentence is to be able to use it in expected ways in communicative interactions with members of one's linguistic community, which involves graded recognitional and inferential ability that often goes well beyond a cognitive grasp of content. The semantic knowledge in question is also unnecessary for understanding a sentence because, as I will argue in chapters 2 and 4, to understand S is to be disposed to use S to entertain p—which, contrary to what is often assumed, doesn't require being disposed to make p the object of one's thought, or to predicate any relation holding between S and p. Once we have a proper understanding of what propositions really are, it will be easy to see that to entertain one is not to have any thought about or cognition of it at all, but to perform the cognitive operations in terms of which the proposition is defined.

This brings me to the final, and most foundational, change in the theoretical framework needed in our quest for a truly scientific study of language and information. Up to now, theorists have identified the semantic content of a sentence with information that represents the world as being a certain way, but they haven't yet given a plausible story about what such a piece of information is, whether linguistically encoded or not. This is our most urgent task, and the one on which I will concentrate most.

The currently dominant semantic approach correctly maintains that S represents things as being a certain way, and so has truth conditions, because the information S encodes—the proposition it expresses—represents things that way, and so has truth conditions. However, it misidentifies those propositions as functions from possible world-states to truth values, or, more simply, as sets of possible world-states (or other truth-supporting circumstances). However, neither such functions nor such sets can play the four roles typically demanded of propositions: (i) the primary bearers of truth and falsity, (ii) the objects of belief, assertion, and other attitudes, (iii) the contents of perceptual and cognitive states, and (iv) the meanings of (some) sentences. There are three main reasons that support this negative conclusion.


(Continues...)
Excerpted from Rethinking Language, Mind, and Meaning by SCOTT SOAMES. Copyright © 2015 Princeton University Press. Excerpted by permission of PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS.
All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

"About this title" may belong to another edition of this title.

  • PublisherPrinceton University Press
  • Publication date2015
  • ISBN 10 0691160457
  • ISBN 13 9780691160450
  • BindingHardcover
  • LanguageEnglish
  • Number of pages256

Buy Used

Condition: As New
Unread book in perfect condition...
View this item

FREE shipping within United Kingdom

Destination, rates & speeds

Other Popular Editions of the Same Title

9780691211497: Rethinking Language, Mind, and Meaning: 5 (Carl G. Hempel Lecture Series)

Featured Edition

ISBN 10:  0691211493 ISBN 13:  9780691211497
Publisher: Princeton University Press, 2020
Softcover

Search results for Rethinking Language, Mind, and Meaning (Carl G. Hempel...

Seller Image

Soames, Scott
Published by Princeton University Press, 2015
ISBN 10: 0691160457 ISBN 13: 9780691160450
Used Hardcover

Seller: GreatBookPricesUK, Woodford Green, United Kingdom

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Condition: As New. Unread book in perfect condition. Seller Inventory # 22088286

Contact seller

Buy Used

£ 32.93
Convert currency
Shipping: FREE
Within United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 1 available

Add to basket

Stock Image

Soames, Scott
Published by Princeton University Press, 2015
ISBN 10: 0691160457 ISBN 13: 9780691160450
New Hardcover

Seller: Ria Christie Collections, Uxbridge, United Kingdom

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Condition: New. In. Seller Inventory # ria9780691160450_new

Contact seller

Buy New

£ 35.88
Convert currency
Shipping: FREE
Within United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 2 available

Add to basket

Seller Image

Soames, Scott
Published by Princeton University Press, 2015
ISBN 10: 0691160457 ISBN 13: 9780691160450
New Hardcover

Seller: GreatBookPricesUK, Woodford Green, United Kingdom

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Condition: New. Seller Inventory # 22088286-n

Contact seller

Buy New

£ 41.70
Convert currency
Shipping: FREE
Within United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 1 available

Add to basket

Stock Image

Soames, Scott
Published by Princeton Univ Pr, 2015
ISBN 10: 0691160457 ISBN 13: 9780691160450
New Hardcover

Seller: Revaluation Books, Exeter, United Kingdom

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Hardcover. Condition: Brand New. 256 pages. 8.75x5.75x1.00 inches. In Stock. Seller Inventory # __0691160457

Contact seller

Buy New

£ 34.72
Convert currency
Shipping: £ 6.99
Within United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 2 available

Add to basket

Stock Image

Scott Soames
Published by Princeton University Press, 2015
ISBN 10: 0691160457 ISBN 13: 9780691160450
New Hardcover

Seller: PBShop.store UK, Fairford, GLOS, United Kingdom

Seller rating 4 out of 5 stars 4-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

HRD. Condition: New. New Book. Shipped from UK. Established seller since 2000. Seller Inventory # IB-9780691160450

Contact seller

Buy New

£ 41.89
Convert currency
Shipping: FREE
Within United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 7 available

Add to basket

Stock Image

Scott Soames
Published by Princeton University Press, 2015
ISBN 10: 0691160457 ISBN 13: 9780691160450
New Hardcover

Seller: THE SAINT BOOKSTORE, Southport, United Kingdom

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Hardback. Condition: New. New copy - Usually dispatched within 4 working days. 482. Seller Inventory # B9780691160450

Contact seller

Buy New

£ 42.34
Convert currency
Shipping: FREE
Within United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 2 available

Add to basket

Stock Image

Scott Soames
Published by Princeton University Press, 2015
ISBN 10: 0691160457 ISBN 13: 9780691160450
New Hardcover

Seller: PBShop.store US, Wood Dale, IL, U.S.A.

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

HRD. Condition: New. New Book. Shipped from UK. Established seller since 2000. Seller Inventory # IB-9780691160450

Contact seller

Buy New

£ 45.93
Convert currency
Shipping: FREE
From U.S.A. to United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 7 available

Add to basket

Seller Image

Soames, Scott
Published by Princeton University Press, 2015
ISBN 10: 0691160457 ISBN 13: 9780691160450
Used Hardcover

Seller: GreatBookPrices, Columbia, MD, U.S.A.

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Condition: As New. Unread book in perfect condition. Seller Inventory # 22088286

Contact seller

Buy Used

£ 31.58
Convert currency
Shipping: £ 14.90
From U.S.A. to United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 1 available

Add to basket

Seller Image

Scott Soames
ISBN 10: 0691160457 ISBN 13: 9780691160450
New Hardcover

Seller: CitiRetail, Stevenage, United Kingdom

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Hardcover. Condition: new. Hardcover. In this book, Scott Soames argues that the revolution in the study of language and mind that has taken place since the late nineteenth century must be rethought. The central insight in the reigning tradition is that propositions are representational. To know the meaning of a sentence or the content of a belief requires knowing which things it represents as being which ways, and therefore knowing what the world must be like if it is to conform to how the sentence or belief represents it. These are truth conditions of the sentence or belief. But meanings and representational contents are not truth conditions, and there is more to propositions than representational content. In addition to imposing conditions the world must satisfy if it is to be true, a proposition may also impose conditions on minds that entertain it. The study of mind and language cannot advance further without a conception of propositions that allows them to have contents of both of these sorts. Soames provides it.He does so by arguing that propositions are repeatable, purely representational cognitive acts or operations that represent the world as being a certain way, while requiring minds that perform them to satisfy certain cognitive conditions. Because they have these two types of content--one facing the world and one facing the mind--pairs of propositions can be representationally identical but cognitively distinct. Using this breakthrough, Soames offers new solutions to several of the most perplexing problems in the philosophy of language and mind. In this book, Scott Soames argues that the revolution in the study of language and mind that has taken place since the late nineteenth century must be rethought. The central insight in the reigning tradition is that propositions are representational. To know the meaning of a sentence or the content of a belief requires knowing which things it repre Shipping may be from our UK warehouse or from our Australian or US warehouses, depending on stock availability. Seller Inventory # 9780691160450

Contact seller

Buy New

£ 48.49
Convert currency
Shipping: FREE
Within United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 1 available

Add to basket

Seller Image

Soames, Scott
Published by Princeton University Press, 2015
ISBN 10: 0691160457 ISBN 13: 9780691160450
New Hardcover

Seller: GreatBookPrices, Columbia, MD, U.S.A.

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Condition: New. Seller Inventory # 22088286-n

Contact seller

Buy New

£ 36.15
Convert currency
Shipping: £ 14.90
From U.S.A. to United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 1 available

Add to basket

There are 11 more copies of this book

View all search results for this book