Items related to The Ecological Detective: Confronting Models with Data:...

The Ecological Detective: Confronting Models with Data: 28 (Monographs in Population Biology, 28) - Softcover

 
9780691034973: The Ecological Detective: Confronting Models with Data: 28 (Monographs in Population Biology, 28)

Synopsis

The modern ecologist usually works in both the field and laboratory, uses statistics and computers, and often works with ecological concepts that are model-based, if not model-driven. How do we make the field and laboratory coherent? How do we link models and data? How do we use statistics to help experimentation? How do we integrate modeling and statistics? How do we confront multiple hypotheses with data and assign degrees of belief to different hypotheses? How do we deal with time series (in which data are linked from one measurement to the next) or put multiple sources of data into one inferential framework? These are the kinds of questions asked and answered by The Ecological Detective. Ray Hilborn and Marc Mangel investigate ecological data much as a detective would investigate a crime scene by trying different hypotheses until a coherent picture emerges. The book is not a set of pat statistical procedures but rather an approach. The Ecological Detective makes liberal use of computer programming for the generation of hypotheses, exploration of data, and the comparison of different models. The authors' attitude is one of exploration, both statistical and graphical. The background required is minimal, so that students with an undergraduate course in statistics and ecology can profitably add this work to their tool-kit for solving ecological problems.

"synopsis" may belong to another edition of this title.

About the Author

Ray Hilborn is Professor in the School of Fisheries, University of Washington and the coauthor, with Carl Walters, of Quantitative Fisheries Stock Assessment. Marc Mangel is Professor of Environmental Studies and a Fellow at College Eight at the University of California, Santa Cruz, and a Visiting Professor at the University of Glasgow. He is the author of Decision and Control in Uncertain Resource Systems and coauthor, with Colin Clark, of Dynamic Modeling in Behavioral Ecology.

Excerpt. © Reprinted by permission. All rights reserved.

The Ecological Detective

Confronting Models with DataBy RAY HILBORN MARC MANGEL

PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS

Copyright © 1997 Princeton University Press
All right reserved.

ISBN: 978-0-691-03497-3

Contents

Preface: Beyond the Null Hypothesis...................................................................xi1. An Ecological Scenario and the Tools of the Ecological Detective...................................32. Alternative Views of the Scientific Method and of Modeling.........................................123. Probability and Probability Models: Know Your Data.................................................394. Incidental Catch in Fisheries: Seabirds in the New Zealand Squid Trawl Fishery.....................945. The Confrontation: Sum of Squares..................................................................1066. The Evolutionary Ecology of Insect Oviposition Behavior............................................1187. The Confrontation: Likelihood and Maximum Likelihood...............................................1318. Conservation Biology of Wildebeest in the Serengeti................................................1809. The Confrontation: Bayesian Goodness of Fit........................................................20310. Management of Hake Fisheries in Namibia Motivation................................................23511. The Confrontation: Understanding How the Best Fit Is Found........................................263Appendix: "The Method of Multiple Working Hypotheses" by T C. Chamberlain............................281References............................................................................................295Index.................................................................................................309

Chapter One

An Ecological Scenario and the Tools of the Ecological Detective

AN ECOLOGICAL SCENARIO

The Mediterranean fruit fly (medfly), Ceratitis capitata (Wiedemann), is one of the most destructive agricultural pests in the world, causing millions of dollars of damage each year. In California, climatic and host conditions are right for establishment of the medfly; this causes considerable concern. In Southern California, populations of medfly have shown sporadic outbreaks (evidenced by trap catch) over the last two decades (Figure 1.1). Until 1991, the accepted view was that each outbreak of the medfly corresponded to a "new" invasion, started by somebody accidentally bringing flies into the state (presumably with rotten fruit). In 1991, our colleague James Carey challenged this view (Carey 1991) and proposed two possible models concerning medfly outbreaks (Figure 1.2). The first model, MJ, corresponds to the accepted view: each outbreak of medfly is caused by a new colonization event. After successful colonization, the population grows until it exceeds the detection level and an "invasion" is recorded and eradicated. The second model, M2, is based on the assumption that the medfly has established itself in California at one or more suitable sites, but that, in general, conditions cause the population to remain below the level for detection. On occasion, however, conditions change and the population begins to grow in time and spread over space until detection occurs. Carey argued that the temporal and spatial distributions of trap catch indicate that the medfly may be permanently established in the Los Angeles area. Knowing which of these views is more correct is important from a number of perspectives, including the basic biology of invasions and the implications of an established pest all agricultural practices.

Determining which model is more consistent with the data is a problem in ecological detection. That is, if we allow that either model M1 or model M2 is true, we would like to associate probabilities, given the data, with the two models. We shall refer to this as "the probability of the model" or the "degree of belief in the mode!." How might such a problem be solved? First, we must characterize the available data, which are the spatial distribution of trap catches of medfly over time (Figure 1.3). We could refine these by placing small grids over the maps and characterizing a variable that measures the number of flies that appear in cell i in year y. Second, we must convert the pictorial or verbal models shown in Figure 1.2 into mathematical descriptions. That is, some kind of mathematical model is needed so that the data can be compared with predictions of a model. Such models would be used to predict the temporal and spatial patterns in detected outbreaks; the mathematical descriptions would generate maps similar to the figures. The models would involve at least two submodels, one for the population dynamics and one for the detection process. Courses in ecological modeling show how this is done. Third, we confront the models with the data by comparing the predicted and observed results. At least three approaches can be broadly identified for such a confrontation.

Classical Hypothesis Testing. Here we confront each model separately with the data. Thus, we begin with hypotheses:

H0: Model M1 is true

Ha: Some other model is true

Here the alternate model might be that outbreaks are random over time and space. Using the mathematical descriptions of the models, we construct a "p value" for the hypothesis that M1 is true. It might happen that we can definitely reject H0 because the p value is so small (usually less than 0.05 or 0.01). Alternatively, we might not be able to reject H0 (i.e., p > 0.05), but then might discover that the power of the statistical test is quite low (we assume that most readers are probably familiar with the terms "p values" and "power" from courses in elementary statistics, but we shall explain them in more detail in the following chapters). In any case, we use such hypothesis testing because it gives the "illusion of objectivity" (Berger and Berry 1988; Shaver 1993; Cohen 1994).

After we had tested the hypothesis that model 1 is true against the alternate hypothesis, we would test the hypothesis that model 2 is true against the alternate. Some of the outcomes of this procedure could be: (i) both models M1 and M2 are rejected; (ii) model M, is rejected but M2 is not; (iii) model M1 is not rejected but M2 is; and (iv) neither model is rejected. If outcome (ii) or (iii) occurs, then we will presumably act as if model M1 or M2 were true and make scientific and policy decisions on that basis, but if outcome (i) or (iv) occurs, what are we to do? Other than collecting more data, we are provided with little guidance concerning how we should now view the models and what they tell us about the world. There is also a chance that if outcome (ii) or (iii) occurs, the result is wrong, and then on what basis do we choose the p level?

Likelihood Approach (Edwards 1992). In this case, we use the data to arbitrate between the two models. That is, given the data and a mathematical description of the two models. we can ask, "How likely are the data, given the model?" Details of how to do this are given in the rest of this book, but read on pretending that you indeed know how to do it. Thus, we first construct a measure of the probability of the observed data, given that the model is true—we shall denote this by Pr{data|Mi}. We then turn this on its head and interpret it as a measure of the chance that the model is the appropriate description of the world, given the data. This is called the likelihood and we denote it by Li{Mi|data}. We now compare the likelihoods of the two models, given the data. If Li{M1|data} >> L2{M2|data}, then we would argue that model M1 is a better description of the world; if L1{M1|data} ~ L2{M2|data}, then we would argue that model M2 is a better description of the world; and if :P1{Mjldata} - c'fA:v1 2 Idata}, then we would argue that the data do not differentiate between the models. A smart decision maker would not act as if the most likely model were true, but would weigh the costs and consequences of each action against the relative probabilities of the alternative hypotheses. But what exactly is meant by ">>," "<<," or "~" in this approach?

In this book, we shall work out methods for determining when one likelihood is much larger than another, and what that means in terms of confronting models with data.

Bayesian Approach. Finally, we might have other information that allows us to judge a priori which model is more likely to be true. For example, we might know the ecology of invasion and establishment of medfly in other places. Or we might know that before certain outbreaks people had been caught bringing fruit into the country from places where medfly is established. This kind of information can be summarized in a "prior probability that model Mi is true," which we denote by pi. If we allow only two models of the world (medfly are established or they reinvade), then p1 + p2 = 1. Now, given information consisting of trap catches and the mathematical model, we want to "update" these prior probabilities. That is, we want to evaluate a "posterior probability that model Mi is true, given the data." Procedures for doing this require an understanding of conditional probability and are generally called "Bayesian methods." named after the Reverend Thomas Bayes, who introduced such ideas. In biology and mathematics, one of the earliest modern proponents was Sir Harold Jeffreys (1948), who called the method "inverse probability." His goal was to find methods that allow us to combine prior information with the chance of observing the data to evaluate a posterior probability of different hypotheses, given a scenario associated with the prior information. Interestingly, although Jeffreys is most famous for his work in applied mathematics, astronomy, and geophysics, he was one of the earliest contributors to the Journal of Ecology (Sheail 1989). In this book, we shall illustrate how Bayesian methods can be developed and applied. They are particularly appropriate for cases in which studies cannot be replicated (e.g., Reckhow 1990) and for assessment of the risk and safety in various environmental settings in which "expert opinion" is sought (Emlen 1989; Apostolakis 1990; Bolt 1991). There are arguments that Bayesian reasoning is the only way to provide a unified and consistent approach to deterministic and statistical theories (Howson and Urbach 1989, 1991).

This ecological scenario illustrates three approaches that can be taken when confronting models with data. It is our opinion that the process of science consists of confronting more than one description of how the world works with data. Thus, in the rest of the book we spend little time on classical methods of hypothesis testing but focus on likelihood and Bayesian methods. Two recent special features in the journal Ecology contain a number of papers that deal with nonclassical approaches to the use of statistics in ecological problems (Carpenter 1990; Jassby and Powell 1990; Reckhow 1990; Walters and Holling 1990; Potvin and Roff 1993; Potvin and Travis 1993; Shaw and Mitchell-Olds 1993; Trexler and Travis 1993) or with particularities of ecological situations (Dutilleul 1993; Legendre 1993). They provide a good complementary background for this book.

THE TOOLS FOR ECOLOGICAL DETECTION

The modern ecologist usually works in both the field and laboratory, uses statistics and computers, and often works with ecological concepts that are model based, if not model driven. How do we make the field and laboratory coherent? How do we link models and data? How do we use statistics to help experimentation? How do we integrate modeling and statistics? How do we confront multiple hypotheses with data and assign degrees of belief to different hypotheses? How do we deal with time series (in which data are linked from one measurement to the next) or put multiple sources of data into one inferential framework? These are the kinds of questions asked and answered by the ecological detective.

Like all other forms of creative activity, ecological detection is a craft that requires the right tools as well as the skills and materials to use the tools. We envision four components.

Hypotheses are the first component. Notice the plural, which is essential to our viewpoint. Science consists of confronting different descriptions of how the world works with data, using the data to arbitrate between the different descriptions, and using the "best" description to make additional predictions or decisions. These descriptions of how the world might work are hypotheses, and often they can be translated into quantitative predictions via models. In Chapter 2, we review different kinds of models, the purposes of models, and how models are related to hypotheses.

Data are the second component. You cannot do good analysis if the data are not good. But what does "good" mean? Sometimes the role of analysis is to show that a set of data-at least within the context of a particular view of the world-is not as informative or as useful as one thought it would be. In Chapter 3, we stress that it is important to "Know Your Data" and we provide a sufficient review of probability and the stochastic processes that you will need to conduct the work of the ecological detective.

Goodness of fit is the third component. When the data are used to arbitrate between different hypótheses or models, we must have a measure to determine how well each description of the world fits the observations. In Chapters 5, 7, and 9, we describe a variety of measures of goodness of fit that can be used in the confrontation of models and data. We provide recommendations about when it is good to use a particular method.

Numerical procedures are the fourth component. Having a measure of goodness of fit between the model and the data is not enough-you must to be able to evaluate it quickly and efficiently and explore the goodness of fit of other models. Thus, in Chapter II, we provide an introduction to numerical methods needed to assess goodness of fit and to find the best fit. There is a history of the use of numerical procedures in ecology (examples from a generation ago are given by Conway et al. 1970, Melzer 1970, and Marten et al. 1975), but it is the development of microcomputers that really allows the full richness of numerical procedures to be exploited by practicing ecologists.

Overarching these components are alternative views of the scientific method and the role of models in science, which we discuss in Chapter 2. There we present four of the major philosophies of science and show how two of them are closely connected to our work of ecological detection.

A final warning. We are practicing ecologists. We are not statisticians, numerical analysts, or philosophers, and the appropriate chapters will no doubt offend the appropriate experts. For this we make no apologies other than stressing that for the ecological detective the problem is paramount. Because of that, we bring to the problem whatever techniques—from wherever they come—needed to solve it. And if the techniques do not exist, then we must invent them.

Chapter Two

Alternative Views of the Scientific Method and of Modeling

Science is a process for learning about nature in which competing ideas about how the world works are measured against observations (Feynman 1965, 1985). Because our descriptions of the world are almost always incomplete and our measurements involve uncertainty. and inaccuracy, we require methods for assessing the concordance of the competing ideas and the observations. These methods generally constitute the field of statistics (Stigler 1986). Our purpose in writing this book is to provide ecologists with additional tools to make this process more efficient. Most of the material provided in subsequent chapters deals with formal tools for evaluating the confrontation between ideas and data, but before we delve into the methods we step back and consider the scientific process itself. No scientist can be truly "neutral." We all operate within a fundamental philosophical worldview, and the types of statistical tools we employ and the types of experiments we do depend on that philosophy. Here we present four such philosophies.

There is a commonly accepted model for the scientific process (and from it arose a well-developed body of statistics that is taught in nearly every university in North America). The basic view can be thought of as a learning tree of critical experiments, which was described by Platt (1964) as "strong inference," and consists of the following steps:

1. Devising alternative hypotheses

2. Devising a crucial experiment (or several of them) with alternative possible outcomes, each of which will, as nearly as possible, exclude one or more of the hypotheses

3. Carrying out the experiment so as to get a clean result

4. Recycling the procedure, making subhypotheses or sequential hypotheses to refine the possibilities that remain, and so on (Platt 1964, 347)

Platt likens this to climbing a tree, where each fork of the tree corresponds to an experimental outcome, and we base the direction of the climb on the outcomes so far. It is especially interesting for us as ecologists that Platt associates a "second great intellectual revolution" with the "method of multiple hypotheses," and attributes some of the most original thinking in this area to the geologist T. C. Chamberlain who published at the end of the last century. In particular, Chamberlain stressed that we are guaranteed to get into trouble when we consider only a single hypothesis rather than multiple hypotheses. This is especially interesting because the similarities between the geological and ecological sciences are in some ways much greater than the similarities between the other physical and the ecological sciences. In both ecology and geology, experiments may be difficult to perform and so we must rely on observation, inference, good thinking, and models to guide our understanding of the world. In fact, ecology may be much more of an "earth science" than a "biological science" (Roughgarden et al. 1994). We include a reprint of Chamberlain's classic paper—first published in the lS90s—as the Appendix.

(Continues...)


Excerpted from The Ecological Detectiveby RAY HILBORN MARC MANGEL Copyright © 1997 by Princeton University Press. Excerpted by permission of PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS. All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.
Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.

"About this title" may belong to another edition of this title.

  • PublisherPrinceton University Press
  • Publication date1997
  • ISBN 10 0691034974
  • ISBN 13 9780691034973
  • BindingPaperback
  • LanguageEnglish
  • Edition number1
  • Number of pages336

Buy Used

Condition: Good
Ships from the UK. Former library...
View this item

FREE shipping within United Kingdom

Destination, rates & speeds

Buy New

View this item

FREE shipping from U.S.A. to United Kingdom

Destination, rates & speeds

Other Popular Editions of the Same Title

9780691034966: The Ecological Detective – Confronting Models With Data: Confronting Models with Data (MPB-28) (Monographs in Population Biology, 28)

Featured Edition

ISBN 10:  0691034966 ISBN 13:  9780691034966
Publisher: Princeton University Press, 1997
Hardcover

Search results for The Ecological Detective: Confronting Models with Data:...

Stock Image

Mangel, Marc, Hilborn, Ray
Published by Princeton University Press, 1997
ISBN 10: 0691034974 ISBN 13: 9780691034973
Used Softcover

Seller: Better World Books Ltd, Dunfermline, United Kingdom

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Condition: Good. Ships from the UK. Former library book; may include library markings. Used book that is in clean, average condition without any missing pages. Seller Inventory # GRP91018319

Contact seller

Buy Used

£ 21.14
Convert currency
Shipping: FREE
Within United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 1 available

Add to basket

Stock Image

Hilborn, Ray
Published by Princeton University Press, 1997
ISBN 10: 0691034974 ISBN 13: 9780691034973
Used Softcover

Seller: Phatpocket Limited, Waltham Abbey, HERTS, United Kingdom

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Condition: Good. Your purchase helps support Sri Lankan Children's Charity 'The Rainbow Centre'. Ex-library, so some stamps and wear, but in good overall condition. Our donations to The Rainbow Centre have helped provide an education and a safe haven to hundreds of children who live in appalling conditions. Seller Inventory # Z1-V-021-02638

Contact seller

Buy Used

£ 23.69
Convert currency
Shipping: £ 2.74
Within United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 3 available

Add to basket

Stock Image

Hilborn, Ray; Mangel, Marc
Published by Princeton University Press, 1997
ISBN 10: 0691034974 ISBN 13: 9780691034973
Used Paperback First Edition

Seller: Tin Can Mailman, Arcata, Arcata, CA, U.S.A.

Seller rating 4 out of 5 stars 4-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Paperback. Condition: Very Good. 1st. Very good condition. Spine is well bound. Text block is unmarked. Minor shelf wear. Seller Inventory # SKU1013024

Contact seller

Buy Used

£ 23.03
Convert currency
Shipping: £ 28.32
From U.S.A. to United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 1 available

Add to basket

Stock Image

0
Published by Princeton University Press, 1997
ISBN 10: 0691034974 ISBN 13: 9780691034973
New Softcover

Seller: Basi6 International, Irving, TX, U.S.A.

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Condition: Brand New. New. US edition. Expediting shipping for all USA and Europe orders excluding PO Box. Excellent Customer Service. Seller Inventory # ABEJUNE24-17529

Contact seller

Buy New

£ 54.08
Convert currency
Shipping: FREE
From U.S.A. to United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 6 available

Add to basket

Stock Image

Hilborn Ray Mangel Marc
Published by Princeton University Press, 1997
ISBN 10: 0691034974 ISBN 13: 9780691034973
New Softcover

Seller: Majestic Books, Hounslow, United Kingdom

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Condition: New. pp. 336. Seller Inventory # 8063456

Contact seller

Buy New

£ 53.90
Convert currency
Shipping: £ 3.35
Within United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 1 available

Add to basket

Stock Image

Ray Hilborn Marc Mangel
Published by Princeton University Press, 1997
ISBN 10: 0691034974 ISBN 13: 9780691034973
New Softcover

Seller: Books Puddle, New York, NY, U.S.A.

Seller rating 4 out of 5 stars 4-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Condition: New. pp. 336 Index. Seller Inventory # 26833087

Contact seller

Buy New

£ 53.43
Convert currency
Shipping: £ 6.71
From U.S.A. to United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 1 available

Add to basket

Seller Image

Hilborn, Ray; Mangel, Marc
Published by Princeton University Press, 1997
ISBN 10: 0691034974 ISBN 13: 9780691034973
New Softcover

Seller: GreatBookPricesUK, Woodford Green, United Kingdom

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Condition: New. Seller Inventory # 401492-n

Contact seller

Buy New

£ 60.23
Convert currency
Shipping: FREE
Within United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 10 available

Add to basket

Stock Image

Hilborn Ray Mangel Marc
Published by Princeton University Press, 1997
ISBN 10: 0691034974 ISBN 13: 9780691034973
New Softcover

Seller: Biblios, Frankfurt am main, HESSE, Germany

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Condition: New. pp. 336. Seller Inventory # 18833077

Contact seller

Buy New

£ 56.89
Convert currency
Shipping: £ 6.71
From Germany to United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 1 available

Add to basket

Stock Image

Ray Hilborn
Published by Princeton University Press, 1997
ISBN 10: 0691034974 ISBN 13: 9780691034973
New PAP

Seller: PBShop.store US, Wood Dale, IL, U.S.A.

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

PAP. Condition: New. New Book. Shipped from UK. Established seller since 2000. Seller Inventory # WP-9780691034973

Contact seller

Buy New

£ 65.69
Convert currency
Shipping: FREE
From U.S.A. to United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 9 available

Add to basket

Seller Image

Hilborn, Ray; Mangel, Marc
Published by Princeton University Press, 1997
ISBN 10: 0691034974 ISBN 13: 9780691034973
Used Softcover

Seller: GreatBookPrices, Columbia, MD, U.S.A.

Seller rating 5 out of 5 stars 5-star rating, Learn more about seller ratings

Condition: good. May show signs of wear, highlighting, writing, and previous use. This item may be a former library book with typical markings. No guarantee on products that contain supplements Your satisfaction is 100% guaranteed. Twenty-five year bookseller with shipments to over fifty million happy customers. Seller Inventory # 401492-5

Contact seller

Buy Used

£ 56.27
Convert currency
Shipping: £ 14.90
From U.S.A. to United Kingdom
Destination, rates & speeds

Quantity: 2 available

Add to basket

There are 23 more copies of this book

View all search results for this book